BOOK REVIEW The Pitfalls of ?Scientific? Feminism Jorm Wallets/3 Scott Deceptive Distinctions.- Sex, Gender; and [be Sorrel Order by Fuchs Epstein. Yale University Press, 1988, 300 pp. ate last year, the New liar/e Times ran an article that heralded two scienti?c ?ndings on sex differences. The placement of the article?in the upper left-hand column of the front page?and its headline? ?Female Sex Hormone Is Tied to Ability to Perform Tasks??suggested the edi- tors? glee at having new evidence to support their views about the natural, if only periodic, incapacity of women for decision making. Not only did the research indicate that biology is destiny (as far as females are concerned), but the fact that the scientists conducting it were women added to its importance. What interest ether than objectivity, after all, could two women have in producing these kinds of results? The Times report and the study it recounted are depressing reminders of the power both of culture to shape science and of scientific appeals to the ?natural? to legitimize inequality. They are also indicators of an ongoing con- test about gender in our society. This contest has high Stakes, for it is about whose conceptions of the relations be- tween the sexes will organize ?reality.? Yet the very terms of debate most often obscure the purpose of the contest. For instead of focusing on what the desir- able forms ofsocial organization might be and how they can be obtained, the contesting sides ?rst argue about the nature of the preexisting reality to which societies must correspond. In the case of gender, this means deciding whether men and women are equal jam; Wallet/J Scott is a professor of social science at the Institute for Ad- vanced Study. Her most recent book is Gender and the Politics of History (Columbia University Press, 1988). 90 TIKKUN VOL. 4, N0. 2 (that is, the same) or different. In the discourse of the sciences [natural or social), access to ?reality? is said to result from objective investi- gation and neutral methodology. The problem, of course, as most philo- sophical writing over the last thirty years on these questions has pointed out, is that reality exists only through its signi?cation, only through processes of conceptualization that confer mean- ing on things, make sense of them. There can be, then, no perfect method of inquiry conducted ourside or apart from language, hence no guarantee of the ultimate truth of any investigation. In this situation, the best reply to re- search such as that reported in the Times is not a condemnation of its inaccuracy but a critique of any notion that objec- tivity is possible. The discussion needs to be directed away from what is ?nat- ural" toward what is socially desirable. Although, in recent years, feminist scholars have developed important cri- tiques of scienti?c discourses of objec- tivity, much of the work on gender in the social sciences has not taken those critiques into account. Instead, research has been designed to prove either that sexual difference is fundamental to pet- sonality and social behavior or that it is irrelevant, that women are different from or equal to men. Fuchs Epstein's book, a general review of the social sci~ enti?c literature on the equality side of the gender debate, provides an example of the dif?culties?and, I think, the ul- timate futility?ofresting arguments for social change on claims to objectivity. Epstein surveyed work not only in her own ?eld of sociology, but also in the allied fields of and anthropology. Her goal was to detach factual truths from ideological debates: have aimed for objectivity in assess- ing the research, but I acknowledge a bias for equality. I believe my bias ?ts the evidence." Epstein?s argument is that men and women are fundamentally similar; re- search that has shown otherwise is biased, blinded by prejudice, wrong- minded, confused, flawed, grounded in ideology or culture [rather than] in systematic observation.? In contrast, her own research and that which sup- ports her position is described as ?objective, gender-free analysis." It is ?correct knowledge? that can confi- dently displace ?old and inaccurate conceptions." EpStein offers little de- tailed analysis of the differences in research methodologies that lead either to biased or correct conclusions. In fact, her reasoning is tautological: we can tell that research is biased if it con- ?rms gender differences; we know it is objective if it disputes them. Further, Epstein does not undetsrand that scien- tific claims for "objectivity" are them- selves ideological, that they can work to legitimize the authority of certain systems of knowledge by grounding them in ?nature? or ?fact? when they are but social consrrucrions. Her main point is that assumptions about?dichot- omous distinctions? between the sexes cannot produce objecrive results. (Ap- parently the prohibition of dichotomy applies only to discussions of gender, because Epstein?s book is built on a series of other dichotomies: research that is true or false, that is biased or objective, that proves equality or dif- ference, that is old and inaccurate or new and untrue.) ccording to Epstein, ?dichotomous distinctions" make it dif?cult to see variety within gender categories and thus similarities across gender lines. I agree with that point, but I don't think denying the "reality" of gender distinctions is an effective way to advance discussion. Those distinc- tions are part of the reality we confront, not only in social science research, but in institutions and organizations as dis- parate as schools, churches. families, and the New Ebola Tri?es. If we deny the reality of these distinctions, we cannot account for them or explain their operations; we can understand neither the gendered organization of society nor the gender identi?cation of individuals, except as the result of oppression or bad faith. The way to deal with these distinctions is not to disprove them but to figure out how they work. Here are some of the questions Epstein's approach does not let her ask: Why, if research on sex differ- ences is so flawed, does it have such a powerful appeal?\?l?hat about Epstein's methodology guarantees her arm ob- jectivity when so many researchers for so long have been so unaware of their own biases? How has she managed to stand outside the cultural and ideo- logical constraints of her own time? Or has she? What is it about the current era and current social scien- ti?c thinking that has made possible the transcendence ofhistorical context and conceptual frameworks, thus per- mitting the discovery of natural or objective ?truth? when doing so has not been possible in earlier periods? If dichoromous distinctions between the sexes are wrong, why haven?t people realized this before? How do the power- ful mechanisms of social comrol?which Epstein says allocate and implement social roles?secure the cooperation of women and men? 801er by force? If notions of socialization and analytic theories are too universal to account for gender identities of women and men [as Epstein suggests), how then can we explain people?s gendered self-identification? Where does insisting that equality is natural and difference ?ideological? get us when we want to understand the effects of ideas? Where does social control (a concept Epstein prefers to socialization) come from? By what processes does it operate? What is the nature of the power it exercises? Epstein?s notion of social control is something imposed from above in the forms of law, public policy, and govern- ment edicts. She doesn?t make clear exactly what is at stake for those with power to enforce rules about gender, except to say that these people have "inveStments in the social order.? Some- times Epstein suggests that men have an interest in subordinating women. denying them equal access to lucrative jobs and the like. At other times she insists that we shouldn?t posit differ- ences of interest by sex; after all, she says, male social scientists have produced unbiased work on equality, while feminists often argue wrongly for difference. Epstein?s analytic confusion about social control comes, I think, frOm an approach that undertheorizes all the important issues: how societies con- struct gender difference, how contra- dictions within even seemingly rigid prescriptions about sexual difference permit variety and change to occur, how individuals establish gender iden- tities. Epstein points out that indi- viduals don't consistently live out the rules of gender, but, instead of ask- ing how and why this discrepancy is possible, she uses it to prove that "ideology" is superimposed on "reality," that women are not really different from men. I am not arguing here that difference is the key to gender, but rather that we cannot dismiss difference as ?wrong? or ?false? and thereby dispel its cultural influence. Instead of disproving the claims of those who argue for sexual difference, we need to relativize and contextualize their arguments. What have been the historical changes in discussions of sexual difference? \?l?hat have been the debates at any point in history and who has taken what side? What have been the effects of the organization of societies according to strict sexual divisions of labor? What is the relationship among normative rules about gender, social institutions such as families, and individual gender identity? hese questions demand answers more complex than those pre- sented in Deceptive Distinctions. For the most part, the research summarized by Epstein and her own approach to the subject oversimplify the issues and perpetuate the dichotomous terms of debate. Dichotomies depend on borh sides of a contrast for their meaning; to refute them, more is required than a simple endorsement of one side or the other. By setting up the discussion as an argument for either equality or difference, and by setting it up in terms of either objectivity or prejudice, Epstein lea?ves open the possibility that her critics will simply reverse the pair- ings, accusing her of subjectively (and blindly) endorsing equality while their objective research proves that men and women are different. The New lime Times article about the effects of estrogen on women's performance is an example of such a reversal. The only way out of this dilemma is to refuse the dichotomous trap entirely, pointing out that nature and objectivity are not the grounds on which to make political claims. Instead, if we want to argue for the equal access of women to jobs, social re- sources, and political rights?we must make the case for equality as a relative matter of justice and politics, not as an absolute question either of scien ce. so- cial science, or nature. Using that case for equality, furthermore, we need not establish that all groups are identical. Rather, equality, in the liberal traditions of political theory within which we Operate, means deliberate indifference to specified differences among indi- viduals and groups. Equality is a right women can claim whether or not they are perceived as or perceive themselves as different. At several points in her book, Ep- stein suggests that the progress of social science has led to greater equality: ?Social science research has been used as the basis for briefs written to rein- terpret and change laws that set differ- ent standards of justice, education, and employment for men and women. And it has resulted on balance in a greater commitment to equality." She continues: revolution in thinking, created by the development of the social sciences and a worldwide shift toward an ideology of equality, has made it possible for the ?rst time in history to seriously question categorical thinking about women and men.? Leaving aside the historical claim, which I think is wrong (categorical thinking about gender has been chal- lenged by feminists in orher centuries, such as Mary Wollstonecraft or John Stuart Mill), I believe that her charac- terization of social science is naive. Only by ruling out as biased or flawed all research that doesn't agree with her point of view (and there continues to be plenty of research that promotes racial as well as sexual difference) can Epstein substantiate her optimism, and this is indeed what she does. But such an approach precludes a more interesting and important kind of analysis of the politics of research in the human sciences. In these ?elds, 91 as in society as a whole, contests about knowledge are contests for power; labels of good and bad, objective and prejudiced, are but weapons in the con- tests. Social science is not then about ?truth,? but about knowledge and its relationship?critical or subservient? to power. BOOK REVIEW I do not mean to deny that things happen, that peOple act, and that these events can be studied systematically. Nor do I want to suggest that, because there is no absolute truth," anything goes. Instead, I want to insist that any critical practice?and I take feminism to be such a practice?must turn its attention to the terms of its own argu- ment and address the disciplinary con- ventions within which it operates. For feminists in the ?eld of social science, a critique of ?objectivity? would be a good place to start. Cl Happiness and the Single Woman Elizabeth Lamhech Worm}: Adrift: Independent Wage Eam- err in Chicago, 1880-1930 by Joanne Meyerowitz. University of Chicago Press, 1988, 224 pp. he ?gure?one might even say the specter?of the single woman has haunted the Anglo-American col- lective imagination from the height of the Victorian era to our own times. This woman, depending on the observer?s point of view, either aggressively spurns male companionship, or is pitifully be- reft of that companionship, or, in the ultimate male fantasy and most-dreaded of respectable womanhood?s nightmares, promiscuously revels in her singleness. The genealogy of these forms is capri- cious and somewhat arbitrary, running from the so-called ?redundant?-?thar is, unmarried?woman of Victorian England; through the pleasingly avail- able flapper of the twenties and her latter-day sister, the sexy career gal of the ?fties; to, ?nally, out culture?s own redundant woman, the hard-bitten, successful careerisr who humiliates men of insuf?cient accomplishment by day and weeps alone for want of these same men by night. This succession of images speaks not only to the enduring mix of antagonism and fascination to which single women have been subject, but also to two signi?cant commonalities. First, each of these representations Eiizaheth Lzmherh teaches history at Princeton University. 92 TIKKUN VOLsimple reflection of the status of ?women? ?whoever they are?but, rather, the product of a real struggle over the very nature of ?womanhood?? single or married. Second, each is, in its many referents, almost exclu- sively middle-class and white; the flap- per is the exception, encompassing a broader spectrum of women and in the right setting?a Harlem jazz club, for exampleetaking on a darker hue. In the progression from one image to the next, we can trace the concur- rent sexualization and trivialization of womanhood?and women?that has been such a salient feature of our recent history. Until feminist historians set out to right the historical record, single Victo- rian women appeared as caricatures? crabbed spinsters and frigid old maids or, when accorded a guarded measure of respect, overeducated bluestockings. But feminist scholars have labored val- iantly to rescue these women from the meager fates contemporaries thought their due. Such historians as Carroll Smith-Rosenberg, Nancy Cort, and Martha Vicinus have successfully recast wretched privation and loneliness into blessed autonomy and sisterhood. At their most daring, they have seen in singlehood a rejection of men and an embrace of women?a women?s culture of loving solidarities that shaded over into what twentieth-century observers, alerted by Freud and a new condemned as lesbianism. This feminist recasting of Victorian- ism was heady stuff. The pinched, narrow, and sexless woman?who em- bodied all the nasty repressiveness that later generations would castigate with the epithet ?Victorian ??was dead, her place taken by a purposeful and ex- pansively sensual paragon of rehabili- tated womanhood. No longer a woman sadly bereft of a man, she was instead one fortunate enough to have escaped the con?nes of the servile?or, at its best, ornamental?domesticity that was the prescribed fate of the nineteenth- century middle-class girl. Locate this new Victorian woman in the urban landscape of the early twen- tieth century, however, and it quickly becomes clear just how limited, how class-bound, a construct she really is. For then, a new, more amorphous group of women?working women, largely, drawn to the city to fill the ranks of the new, pink-collar office and sales occupations?became visible in the public sphere. The focus of the debate about woman?s nature shifted from the middle-class to the working- class woman. Historians have largely missed this shift and have written as if both the ?New Woman" and the flapper? those icons, circa 1920, of mod- ern womanhood?were but Victorians without the repression: middle-class, college-educated, de?antly indepen~ dent of men. The Victorian paradigm of indepen- dent womanhood could neither compre- hend nor accommodate the desires and practices of these new working women. Middle-class and working women of- ten found themselves at odds, the for-