Progress: The Last Superstition Christopher Lose/3 either liberalism nor Marxism, its principal competitor, seems to hold out much hope for solutions to the mounting problems that threaten to overwhelm us. Hence the search for some third position, as evidenced by recent interest in civic humanism, communitarianism, and other submerged traditions of social criticism that have been over- shadowed by the dominant traditions deriving from the Enlightenment. The search for a third way, neither MarxiSt nor liberal, reflects a growing fear that people are no longer in control of their lives. \Whether it is possible to imagine a convincing alter- native to the ideologies that have shaped the modern world and what such an alternative would look like depend on our understanding of just where the old ideologies went wrong. My own view is that the roots of the dif?culty lay in their common commitment to the idea of progress?which is why I am so deeply opposed to an attempt to stake out a new position that continues to define itself as ?progressive.? That way, nothing but confusion lies. The ?rst thing we need to understand is that hope does not demand a belief in progress. It demands a belief in justice: the conviction that the wicked will suffer, that wrongs will be made right. that the underlying order of things is not ?oured with impunity. Hope implies a deep-seated trust in life, which appears absurd to those who lack it. But hope serves us better, in steering troubled waters ahead, than a belief in progress. Not that it prevents us from expecting the worst. On the contrary, the worst is always what the hopeful are prepared for. Their trust in life would not be worth much if it had not survived disappointments in the past, while their knowledge that the future holds further disappointments demonstrates the continuing need for hope. Believers in progress, on the other hand, though they like to think of themselves as the party of hope, actually have little need for it, since they have history on their side. Still, their lack of hope incapacitates them for intelligent action. Improvidence, a blind faith that things will somehow work out for the best, serves Christopher Lesa/?9, a professor of history at the University of Rochester; is a contributing editor to Tikkun. He is the author of The Culture of Narcissism (Norton, 1979) and The Minimal Self (Norton, 1984), and is currenth writing a book called Hope Against Hope: Progress and Its Critics. as a poor substitute for the disposition to see things through even when they don't. This fatalistic optimism, this con?dent assumption that history works on the side of enlightenment, equality, and individual freedom, was the source of Marxism?s nororious indifference to the morality of means and ends?the issue that troubled those who believed that progress was a mixed blessing at best. For Marxists, the choice of means was simple: whatever hastened the proletarian revolution. The ?natural laws of capitalism," Marx said, worked ?with iron necessity towards inevitable results.? This did nor mean that every nation had to go through a bourgeois phase on the way to socialism. \When the Bolsheviks seized power in Russia, they could cite Marx?s statement that Russia might be able to ?obtain the fruits with which capitalist production has enriched humanity without passing through the capitalist regime.? \Without a bourgeois revolution, however, the socialist regime would itself have to do the work of capitalism, beginning with the expropriation of the peasantry; eventually this logic became the rationale for Stalinism in the Soviet Union. The upshot of the Marxian scheme of history was that certain things had to happen in sequence, whether they happened under bourgeois or ?proletarian? auspices: the destruction of the old landed aristocracy; the rise of a new ruling class in its place; the ?annihilation? of small-scale production; the trans- formation of peasants and artisans into wage workers; the replacement of communal, patriarchal, and ?idyllic? arrangements by contractual arrangements; the rise of a new individualism in personal life; the collapse of religion and the spread of scientific habits of thought; the demysti?cation of authority. Some such series of developments had to take place whether anyone wanted them to or not, and no matter what groups happened to be in charge of the state at any given time. Marx ?s theory of history, political philosopher Jon Elster writes, was ?strangely disembodied.? By ?working backward from the end result to preconditions,? it ?could dispense with actors and their intentions.? Because it dispensed with actors, we should add, it could also dispense with questions of politics and morality. According to Marx, socialism would reconcile the individual and society. It represented a ?higher between individualism and ?organic unity.? Elster, a sympathetic critic, finds the indiscriminate solidarity? 27 envisioned by Marx and Engels both unconvincing and a little ominous. People need a ?narrower focus of loyalty and solidarity than the international community of workers,? Elster argues. Altruism ?ourishes in ?small, stable groups? and ?declines as the circle of individuals expands.? ?Free-floating benevolence? is incompatible with ?personal integrity and strength of character.? But Marx could not have acknowledged the value of small, stable groups without sacri?cing his unilinear theory of progress, according to which history moves inexorably in the direction of more and more inclusive forms of solidarity. The liberal theory of progress, on the other hand, is less rigid and therefore more easily reconciled, it seems, with evidence that history does not always move in a single directiOn. It was not the secularization of the Christian belief in Providence that gave rise to the eighteenth-century idea of progress, as is so often alleged, but the more specific assumption that people?s appetites, formerly condemned as a source of social instability and personal unhappiness, could drive the economic machine?just as people?s insatiable curiosity drove the scientific project?and thus insure a never-ending expan- sion of productive forces. The moral rehabilitation of desire generated a new sense of possibility, which an- nounced itself most characteristically not in the vague utopianism of the French Enlightenment but in the hardheaded new science of political economy. For Adam Smith, it was the self-generating character of rising expectations, newly acquired needs and tastes, and new Standards of personal comfort that broke the old cycle of social growth and decay and gave rise to a form of society capable of inde?nite expansion. The decisive break with older ways of thinking came when human needs began to be seen not as natural but as historical and constantly changing, hence insatiable. As the supply of material comforts increased, standards of comfort increased as well, and the category of neces- sities came to include many goods formerly regarded as luxuries. For Smith, the ?uniform, constant, and un- interrupted effort of every man to better his condition? became the ?principle from which public and national, as well as private opulence is originally derived.? Smith?s defense of high wages, unusual for its time, tested on the premise that ?a person who can acquire no property can have no other interest but to eat as much, and to labor as little as possible.? The hope of improving his condition, on the other hand, would encourage Smith?s working man to spend his income on ?things more durable? than the ?hospitality? and ?festivals? preferred by the wealthy; and the accumulated effects of this kind of expenditure, even though they might reflect a ?base and selfish disposition,? would maintain a whole nation of industrious workers. 28 TIKKUN VOL. 4, N0. 3 he history of liberalism, for our present pur- poses, can be seen as the periodic attenuation and abandonment of these ideas, on the one hand, and the periodic rediscovery of them, on the other, by a long line of thinkers, culminating with the pro- ponents of Keynesian economics, who made the most refined attempts to link social progress to the inde?nite expansion of consumer demand. The conCEpt of pro- gress, as the most aStute liberal theorists have under- stood, can be defended against intelligent criticism only by postulating a never-ending expansion of desires, a steady rise in the general standard of comfort, and (most important of all) the continual incorporation of new groups into the culture of consumption. It is only in this form that the idea of progress has survived the calamities of the twentieth century. More extravagant versions of the progressive faith, premised on the per- fectibility of human nature?on the unrealized power of reason or love?collapsed a long time ago, but the liberal version has proved surprisingly resistant to the shocks to easy optimism administered in rapid succession by twentieth-century events. Liberalism was never utopian, unless the democrati- zation of consumption is itself a utopian ideal. It made no difficult demands on human nature. It presupposed nothing more strenuous in the way of motivation than intelligent self-interest. It assumed that almost everyone had a stake in increased productivity, higher wages, shorter hours of work, and a more creative use of leisure. Capitalism, said Horace Kallen, the political philosopher of consumption, had .. raised the general standard of living, transformed scarcity into abun- dance, awakening wants where none had been before, multiplying few into many, bringing more and more varied goods to more people at lower prices, so that what had been formerly, if at all, available only reach of many of those who had produced much and consumed little.? It remained only to complete the capitalist revolution by making the ?blessings of leisure? available to all. No improvement in mental capacity was required in order for the desirability of this goal to be generally recognized; nor did the realiza- tion of the goal require altruism and self-sacri?ce?only a willingness to subordinate short-term pleasure to long- term peace and prosperity. Even this modest level of discipline, however, has prdved dif?cult to sustain in societies propelled by the imperatives of mass consumption. In American politics, the kind of intelligent conservatism that reconciled the business classes to the need for social justice is Clearly on the wane, perhaps because demands for reform voiced from below have grown increasingly faint. During the age of reform, imaginative statesmen like Theodore Roosevelt, Woodrow Wilson, and Franklin D. Roosevelt could cite the radical pressures mounted by Populists, socialists, and militant labor unions as an incentive to implement more modest reforms. For a variety of reasons, however, it has become more and more dif?cult for popular demands to get a hearing. Third parties are weaker than they used to be; the consolidation of the press into a handful of giant chains eliminates small papers and narrows the range of political debate; the dominance of television further encourages this homog- enization of opinion; the growth of the executive branch of government at the expense of the legislature makes of?cials less directly responsible to a popular constitu- ency, while the courts, the least accountable branch of government, have assumed an increasingly important role in policy-making; and the system of direct primaries, instituted in the hope of bringing government closer to the people, has had the opposite effect, increasing the ?nancial resources necessary to mount a successful cam- paign and transferring the selection of candidates from party managers to the mass media more than to the voters. The effect of these changes in making government appear remote and inaccessible to ordinary people is evident in the decline of voting, in widespread political apathy, and in the distrust of \Washington on which the New Right has played so effectively. rom the beginning, liberalism placed less em- phasis on the duties of citizenship than on the right to enjoy the good things of life. The function of the state was to guarantee those rights, not to provide citizens with a political education or to interfere in any way with the pursuit of private advantage. Democ- racy (insofar as it was identi?ed with liberalism at all) thus came to be identi?ed with an equitable distribution of goods rather than with the widest possible participa- tion in public life. A general improvement in the standard of living seemed to justify the choice of distributive democracy over participatory democracy. Recent experi- ence, however, suggests that it may be impossible, in the long run, to achieve one without the other. The favored few cannot be trusted to consult the needs of the many, even when, as Keynes and Kallen pointed out, it is manifestly in their long-term interest to raise the general level of consumption. If the many now enjoy comforts formerly restricted to the few, it is because they have won them through their own political initiative, not because the wealthy have voluntarily surrendered some of their privileges or because the market auto- matically assures abundance for all. The decline of popular initiative in politics, together with the decline of intelligent c0nservatism, therefore wears a menacing look; a steady progress toward equality, to put it mildly, can no longer be taken for granted. Liberalism ultimately presupposes the creatiOn of a global market that embraces populations formerly ex- cluded from any reasonable expectation of affluence. But the prediction that ?sooner or later we will all be affluent,? uttered so con?dently only a few years ago, no longer carries much conviction. The global circula- tion of commodities, information, and populations, far from making everyone af?uent, has widened the gap between rich and poor nations and has generated a massive migration to the West, where the newcomers swell the vast army of the homeless, unemployed, illiterate, drug-ridden, derelict, and effectively disen- franchised. Their presence strains existing resources to the breaking point. Medical and educational facilities, Hope does not demand a belz'efz'n progress. It demands a belief 2'72 justice. law-enforcement agencies, and the job supply?not to mention the supply of racial tolerance and goodwill, never abundant to begin with?all appear inadequate to the enormous task of assimilating what is essentially a surplus or ?redundant? population, in the cruelly expressive British phrase. The poisonous effects of poverty and racial discrimination cannot be ghettoized; they too circulate on a global scale. ?Like the effects of industrial pollution and the new system of global ?nan- cial markets,? Susan Sontag writes, ?the AIDS crisis is evidence of a world in which everything that can circulate does??goods, images, garbage, disease. It is not surprising that ?the look into the future, which was once tied to a vision of linear progress,? has turned into a ?vision of disaster,? in Sontag?s words, and that ?any- thing . . . that can be described as changing steadily can be seen as heading toward catastrophe.? The gist of my argument up to this point is that the consumerist program cannot succeed without popular participation in government and without a heightened sense of civic commitment, both of which, however, tend to be eroded by the consumerist emphasis on private satisfactions [and by many other features of consumerist culture as well). To this we can add a second point: that consumerism requires a global market and a continuation of the trend toward political central- ization, whereas civic participation is far more effective in small COmmunities where people feel directly respon- sible for their actionsthis dilemma except to choose one of its two horns, either equality or economic growth, either citizenship or consumerism. We can?t have both, and there is no point in pretending that PROGRESS: THE LAST SUPERSTITION 29 we can somehow combine ?community? with large-scale organization or civic revival with a continuing commit? ment to a more and more af?uent standard of living. conviction that our progressive society is approaching the end of the road and that we will have to face hard choices in the near future is strengthened by another consideration, namely, the mounting evidence that the earth?s ?nite resources will not support an inde?nite expansion of industrial civilization along its present lines. \Vhile the attempt to maintain the existing standard of living enjoyed by industrial nations without sharing it with the rest of the world would be unconscionable, the attempt to export \Y/estern standards would eventually mean the exhaustion of nonrenewable resources, the irreversible pollution of the earth?s atmosphere, the drastic alteration of its climate, and the destruction, in short, of the ecological system on which human life depends. Rudolph Bahro, a leading spokesman for the West German Greens, writes: Let us imagine what it would mean if the raw material and energy consumption of our society were extended to the four and a half billion people living today, or to the ten to ?fteen billion there will probably be tomorrow. It is readily apparent that the planet can only support such volumes of production for a short time to come. If Bahto is right, we have only two choices: to make the \West more than ever an island of prosperity in a poverty- stricken world, barricading ourselves against our neigh- bors; or to accept a general reduction of our own standard of living. Neither alternative, it hardly needs to be pointed out, is consistent with the ideology of progress. If there is any merit in the sketchy arguments outlined here, they suggest a ?nal point: the need to clarify the communitarian critique of liberalism and to face its social, political, and cultural implications without ?inch- ing. Communitarianism, if that is what we want to call it, does not imply a return to the New Deal, the revival of the progressive tradition in American politics. It implies a repudiation of that tradition. It implies small- scale production, workers? control of industry, and com- munity control of education. It also implies, I think, a 30 TIKKUN VOLwillingness to undergo the risks of public controversy about morality and religion. The exclusion of moral and religious issues frorn politics has been one of the hallmarks of liberalism and one of the preconditions, in all likelihood, of economic progress. It was Only when the separation of church and state put an end to the wars of religion that the West was able to devote itself wholeheartedly to the all-engaging task of increas- ing productivity. Once the state ceased to be the guardian of religious orthodoxy, it could assume what has since come to be recognized as its primary function-?that of keeping the economy in good working order. The price of this policy, however, has been a certain trivialization of public debate. One of the reasons people take so little interest in politics today, aside from the in- accessibility of the bureaucratic structures that dominate political life, is that politics fails to address issues of overriding moral importance. It won?t do, therefore, for communitarians to call for a revival of civic spirit while deploring the right?s attempt to put divisive moral and religious issues on the political agenda. Liberals can consistently argue that such issues are matters of private choice and therefore do not belong in public, but communitarians don?t enjoy that luxury. If they are serious, they will have to engage the religious right on its own terms, recognizing that a community is consti- tuted by vigorous public debate about the issues that really matter, not by universal agreement about those issues. Orestes Brownson once said, always hold that to be important truth, wherein I differ from others.? One of the more farsighted of nineteenth-century social critics, Brownson pointed out that the separation of politics and religion actually led not so much to the exclusion of religion from public life but to a bland, nondenominational civil religion that helped to enforce the socioeconomic status quo. When he criticized the separation of religion and politics, he meant that ques- tions concerning the ?destiny of man? ought to become questions for public debate, not that a new religious establishment should provide authoritative answers- ?Peace is a good thing, but justice is . Give us the noise and contention of life, rather than the peace and silence of the charnel-house.? Communitarians would be well advised to take these words to heart.