PAPERS FROM THE TIKKUN CONFERENCE In the last two issues we have printed several papers and addresses from the Tikkun Conference, which was held in December 1988. Our presentation of conference material is concluded with this special section. We regret that we do not have the space in the future to print more of the many interesting and important ideas that were presented at the conference. PAPER: LIBERALISM AND ITS CRITICS 'Tikkun and Progressive Liberalism Gary Peller ne of Tihhun?s real as a magazine, and as a center for progressive Jewish thought, is its openness to a wide range of political Views and sensibilities. Civil libertarians, feminists, socialists, Marxists, social democrats, and Democratic party liberals are all heard in Tihhun. There is no ?of?cial? Tihhun dogma of the correct way to look at the world. At the same time, amidst the diversity of views, Tihhun has introduced and encouraged a very particular kind of progressive politics, an approach re?ected most strongly in its editorial pages, but also seen in many outside contributions. This new political thinking is character- ized by attention paid to people?s emotional needs, to family relations, to the relevance of religious belief and spiritual insight for political life, to the of power underlying social alienation and passivity, to the loss of con?rmation and meaning people feel in their everyday lives, and to the need for progressives to respond to authentic aspirations people have for a moral vision in which they can feel part of a community collectively re-creating social life. The position has been called ?neocompassionism? or the ?politics of transcendence.? For simplicity?s sake, I will just refer to it as Tikkun politics.? Now this new approach has caused uneasiness among some, and fellow progressives and liberals rather than right-wingers have often been the ones who have reacted most sharply. For example, when Betty Mensch and Alan Freeman wrote about the limiting effects of the public/private dichotomy in liberal ideology, Paul Starr saw ?an image of collective tyranny rarely seen this side of Jonestown? (thun, March/April 1988). When Peter Gabel, Mensch and Freeman, and I criticized what we Gary Peller is a professor of law at Georgetown University Law Center. saw as the colonizing power that scienti?c discourse exercises in the debate between creationism and evolu- tion (Ti/ehun, Nov/Dec. 1987), letters to the editor accused us of engaging in the same kind of irrationality that characterized fascism, the nazism, and other reactionary movements (Tzhhun, May/June 1988). And when Edward Rothstein wrote about the New York Tih/eun conference in the New Republic, it was Michael Lerner?s intermingling of Judaism and politics that he f0und most troubling: ?[T]he claim of any intrinsic connection between politics and religion can only lead to a distortion of both? (New Republic, March 6,1989). These reactions, though sometimes extreme, should not be surprising. Critics are correct when they sense that this new discourse is fundamentally different from the ways that liberals and progressives have usually understood politics. Tihhnn politics is not traditional progressive liberalism with new topics, such as the family and spirituality, sprinkled in to keep up with the times. While we support the progressive agenda for welfare, better housing, child care, antidiscrimination efforts, and strong protection of human rights, we are simultaneously engaged in an effort to get liberals and progressives to rethink their most vital assumptions about politics, power, and the meaning of social reform. We believe that the traditional progressive politics has failed to comprehend the central importance of people?s widespread feelings of powerlessness and alienation as an obstacle to the possibilities for meaningful social change. The progressive liberal agenda has not inspired popular passion because it conceives of politics in too narrow a way, as concerned solely with the distribution of government bene?ts and the protection of individual rights, and thus it fails to present a vision that enlivens progressive proposals with a sense of shared purpose and community by connecting them to people?s everyday 77 lives and experiences. The overarching liberal vision is that progress means enforcing various borders?borders between reason and passion, objective scienti?c knowledge and subjective personal intuition, public politics and private religion, the liberty of the individual and the coercive power of the community. Within this tradition, justice consists of people?s being treated neutrally in public affairs, as citizens, while being free to be particular and subjective in private life, as individuals. Religion is banished from the public realm because its knowledge is subjective and particular, and therefore its presence in the public realm would constitute a tyranny of a part over the whole; science is elevated in the public world because its knowledge is objective and universal. Racial and sexual discrimination are fought against because they represent irrational prejudice; neutral procedures of selection are elevated because they are supposed to treat individuals on their own merits. And thus, when writers in Tz'kkun argue for the relevance of religious intuition and spiritual insight to public life, or assert that science has itself become an ideology of hierarchy and power, or contend that the emotional breakdown of family life and friendships has a social, political dimension, liberals see a violation of deeply assumed borders between politics on the one hand and objective truth and private liberty on the other. his sense of patrolling borders is also evident on the philosophical level, in the shared dualities that mark each liberal category of knowledge. I am going to be ridiculously simplistic here, but I want to draw attention simply to the basic outlines. First of all, this worldview is characterized by a particular ontology which conceives of individual subjects existing in meaningful form prior to social groups. Similar to this ontological separation of the individual from the group is the epistemological separation of objectivity and subjectivity: true knowledge is not the particular intuition of people, but the universalizable proof of reason. Associated with this ontology and epistemology is a liberal genre of social theory that explains how groups come into being and relate to one another. The shared assumption here is that groups are secondary to individuals, so that various social groups (ranging from the state to marriage) are formed on the basis of the consent of formerly separate individuals who express their desire to join with others. And, ?nally, the liberal tradition has an associated political theory of freedom, focused on the preservation of individual liberty from the demands of the collectivity and holding that the best way to accomplish this goal is to prevent the state from imposing contingent values, such as religious beliefs, on individuals. 78 TIKKUN VOL. 4, No. 4 Those of us seeking to transcend the limits of the liberal worldview start with a perception that the prob- lems of our current social reality are more profound than simply the lack of appropriate government programs or the insuf?cient protection of particular individual rights. Rather, we take as a primary task the need to respond to the alienation, disengagement, and power- lessness of people?s day-to-day experience of social life; to the way that we experience our jobs, our friendships, our families, and ourselves; to the loss of the sense that liberalism initially promised that the world is not ?xed and necessary but contingent and open to change?that we can make and remake the world by working together. In our contemporary society, the typical experience of work, say, is not one of engagement and choice, where we feel a part in the creation of our structures of social relations, but rather one of playing out some role that has been written for us by someone else, we know not whom, to which we adapt ourselves to ?t the external demands of whatever our job description is. And the formal democracy of unionism has not, in most places, changed this basic lack of meaning in our work lives. In the same way, the common experience of politics is not an engaged sense that we are part of the day-to-day collective construction of the terms of social life. Rather it is the episodic, alienating isolation of standing in solitary voting booths in order to guarantee the privat- ization of the political moment, standing outside any actual participation like voyeurs in a closet, punching holes in pieces of paper for candidates we don?t really like?as far as we can tell, since they are presented to us through the mediation of professional image produc- tion. The problems of our polity are poverty, home- lessness, and the continued domination of racism and sexism, but what seems to hinder attempts to transform our world is a deeper sense that things can?t change because we aren?t even connected to them, that our ways of relating to each other are external to us, that there is a core necessity to our basic terms of social life?otherwise our rights will be threatened or the trash won?t get picked up. This is the general sense of dis- engagement and resignation that needs to be transcended if our social life is to be meaningfully transformed. Liberalism, at its birth, represented many of the same truths that we hold most central. As a rhetoric of critique against status-based feudal life, liberal ideology was a revolutionary and powerful assertion of the contingency of social life?of the idea that the forms of human association can be radically different and, conversely, that human relations are not objective and ?xed, with an immanent order ?owing from nature, but instead are rooted in social choice and thus can be remade by human will. As a political theory and an intellectual tradition, liberalism was ?rst and foremost a critique of existing social power, a historic assertion that power has no Divine authority but must answer at the citadel of reason. And in more contemporary contexts, this tradition has had heroic moments when people stood up during the McCarthy period for freedom of speech and thought, and during the civil rights struggles of the fifties and sixties when liberals powerfully articulated the injustice of racism and the virtues of equality. he problem is that, today, this tradition no longer inspires or demands reform and resistance. The ?aw of the liberal agenda is not only that it ignores a particularly important dimension of our social lives by failing to address the powerlessness and aliena- tion that has come to characterize our public roles. The difficulty is deeper than that. Today liberalism has become part of an American cultural ideology that legitimates as neutral the basic terms of our social relations and therefore contributes to a sense of neces- sity about existing ways of being together, even as it suggests reforms for exceptional deviations re?ected in ?discrimination? against particular groups. The feudal invocation of Divine authority has been replaced by the enlightened authority of Reason and Science, but they play the same roles?to justify as necessary and impartial what is really social and contingent. Tikkun politics is threatening to people who are used to thinking of social justice according to the traditional categories because our approach denies the virtues of maintaining the borders of liberal ideology. First of all, we are critical of the universalizing notion that it is possible to have a public life that would be simply neutral to particular groups or interests. The constant tendency is to treat as objective and uncontroversial, as free from the marks of power and will, aspects of our public lives that we think are inevitably political and socially constructed?like the idea that, but for race or gender discrimination, people are treated ?on their own merits? in work life; or that, once religious explanations for genesis are excluded, the remaining evolutionary account is neutral or objective; or that, so long as the government has been kept out, our social relations are the result of our private choice. In each of its central oppositions, the liberal ideology is oriented toward a place that would be universal, free from the particularity of politics and history, rational as opposed to intuitive, neutral instead of biased, objective instead of partial, scienti?c and secular rather than intuitive and religious. But this point of view beyond point of View, this universe of reason beyond the particularities of time and place, simply does not exist. This is not merely an academic issue about the intel- lectual possibility of an Archimedean vantage point. The epistemology of liberalism takes on a lived form in particular institutions, as the discourse of rational impersonality becomes the actual voices of those in authority: the voice of the ?expert? educational admin- istrators in school board meetings, of the ?neutral? judge in court, of professional doctors relating to lay patients and corporate executives to workers, and, ?nally, of a widespread cultural neutrality ultimately symbolized by the accentless and disembodied network news anchor speaking with the authority of impersonality. But every time such a point is presented, the claimed universality and objectivity are really the creation of particular people with particular interests and histories and ideologies. Tbe progressive liberal agenda bas not inspired popular passion because it conceives of politics as concerned solely witb tbe distribution of government bene?ts and tbe protection of individual rigbts, and fails to connect to peoples everyday lives and experiences. By orienting itself toward this vantage point of neutrality, the liberal worldview obscures the ways that our social lives are inevitably political and contestable, precisely because they are created by us and therefore can be created differently. For example, the idea that combating racial domination consists simply of removing irrational discrimination against people of color misunderstands what is at stake. It is not simply unequal treatment that constitutes the ideology of white supremacy, but, on a deeper level, the arrogance that once such invidious dis- crimination has been removed the remaining distribution of jobs or other bene?ts would truly re?ect some objec- tive, acultural, neutral standard of ?merit.? To the extent that the traditional liberal approaches understand in- justice as consisting only in treating clearly identified groups with bias, they uncritically legitimate the more general ways that American institutional life is unfairly structured in hierarchies that elevate some people and marginalize others under the guise of a neutral rationality that is presented as beyond politics and free from the marks of social power. To recover the possibility of mass engagement and interest, we must begin to recognize that social relations are contingent across the board?not simply in the possibility of subjective discrimination, but more profoundly in the way that ?objective? criteria of merit and reward are constructed. The distortions of the liberal ideology go beyond this tendency to legitimate particular social relations as TIKKUN AND PROGRESSIVE LIBERALISM 79 neutral and objective. The liberal outlook also misses the everyday politics of our social lives by ?ltering understanding through a sharp dichotomy between a private, individual realm where we are supposed to be free from power and a public, social realm where we are subject to necessary social force. Within the terms of liberal political ideology, the alienation people feel is systematically misperceived as either a ?private? matter or a ?neutral? public necessity, and thus the politics of everyday life is made invisible, and the politics of public life is put out of reach. iberalism?s border between the individual and the group forms the ideological infrastructure within everyday consciousness for the experience of alienation I described earlier. In its most important dimension liberalism is neither an ontology nor a political or philosophical theory; rather, it is a lived ideology about how to be in the world, about how to understand the self in relation to others. In this everyday dimension, liberalism exists as the set of categories we use for experiencing and making sense of the world. The central notion is that, as individuals, we are separate from the groups in which we ?nd ourselves, and that our public lives are sharply distinguished from our private lives. Group life, viewed through this ?lter, is at ?rst alien to us, threatening to rob us of our identities, of our freedom to make what we want of ourselves. So we come into group life distrusting others and seeking protection through ?rights? that mark the boundaries between self and other. In making this quali- tative distinction between public and private, the indi- vidual and the group, the subject and the object, we take the public, social roles we play as normally objective, external to us, part of the demand of the other, precisely because we know we did not choose them. We already knew what the role ?manager? or ?worker? meant before we began playing it. Conversely, we think of our private time as subjective, as free from social power. The trade- off for playing out our public roles without any sense of real meaning or engagement is that when we go home, into our private realm, we are supposed to be free to be ourselves, to act on our individual desires in the realms of sexuality, family life, religious experience, friendship, and play. One consequence of shaping our understanding of social life in this way is a constrained view of the borders of politics, of the regions of social life appro- priate for social struggle. By translating our ?private? lives as based on individual choice and autonomy, the liberal ideology tells us that these issues are not political at all because they should have nothing to do with the exercise of social power. To make private choices the subject of public politics is to engage in moralism, and 80 TIKKUN VOL. 4, N0. 4 that?s what conservatives do. But this translation of our experience is false. Just as our public relations can never be neutral and objective, so too are our so-called private lives inevitably consti- tuted by social power. This is true in one sense because our public roles directly influence our private lives. To the extent that we experience public life as the need to shape ourselves to be acceptable to demands rooted outside, in the objective, out-there forces of the market or some bureaucracy, we begin to form ourselves with an to how others will see us and we lose touch with our?authentic feelings separate from this process. Part of our dif?culty in forming friendships and long-term intimate relationships in our ?private? lives is rooted in the effect of our public roles on our core identities. The in?uence of the social in our ?private? world goes deeper than this spillover from the public world. Social power, re?ected in the very terms we inevitably use for understanding ourselves and each other, is constitutive to our private roles themselves. We approach each other, even in the private realm, according to a public language for perceiving each other?as friend, lover, neighbor, parent, child, stranger, and so on. Our freedom simply to be ourselves is constrained by how others see us and by our need for their acceptance and con?rmation. And each of these private roles carries with it a social meaning about the appropriate boundaries, bearing the terms upon which acceptance has been institutionalized. This is not to say that there is nothing to the individual that ever distinguishes her from the group?only that there is no way to mark off this distinction either in theory or in day-to-day experience. The attempt to separate it out?the animating concern of liberal political thought~inevitably misrepresents what is socially con- structed and political as individual and private. Not- withstanding the role liberal ideology played in building resistance to the oppression of feudal life, in today?s world the category of ?private liberty? can just as easily mean the misrepresentation of social power as mere individual choice and the tendency to blame ourselves for unhappiness that is in fact rooted in social structures. Of course, progressive liberalism now recognizes as public and political certain economic relations that nineteenth-century liberals saw as private. According to the classical liberal ideology, if a worker and an employer ?chose? a particular wage and working condi- tions, the state had no business interfering with their ?rights? because the wage was too low, the working conditions too unsafe or oppressive, or the resulting distribution of wealth t00 lopsided. The New Deal re?ected the widespread rejection of this apologetic ideology. It marked the recognition that economic life is not privately chosen but publicly constituted by the distribution of property and entitlements flowing from the state itself, and that one?s economic status is the result not of a natural market meritocracy, but of politics. Today?s liberals are progressive in their view of the state as an active participant in the achievement of social welfare. Thus progressives attempt to get the government to make economic life more egalitarian even while they maintain traditional liberal vigilance in keeping the state out of areas of individual liberty and private choice. The problem is that, despite its progressive economic policy, contemporary liberalism retains the traditional idea that justice consists in the separation of the pub- lic and the private. Progressive reform has meant the transfer of economic issues to the political arena, but also the preservation of the underlying liberal metaphysic of individualism. he contemporary feminist movement, where the slogan ?the personal is political? originated, has powerfully revealed the social politics of ?private? life. Here the attack on the ideology of the public/private metaphysic has been deeper and more subversive to the liberal worldview because the focus has been on the way the very paradigms of privacy?the family, home life, sexuality, and personal fantasy?are the products of the social power of patriarchal assump- tions. We do not join in family life and sexual relations as autonomous, freely choosing monads acting on our individual, presocial desires. Our family roles and our sexuality, like it or not, are infused with social under- standings of what it means to be a man or a woman, a parent or a child, gay or straight, a mother or a father, a ?housewife? or a wage earner. Even what we find erotic is socially constructed by what the social world has told us about ourselves and our partners, about the normalcy of domination and hierarchy. Whatever one thinks of the particular reform proposals of the feminist antipornography movement, there is no denying that its proponents have powerfully articulated the consti- tutive nature of social power in what many of us take to be our very most private relations, and have demon- strated that the liberal vision of government neutrality, the attempt to keep the state out of our ?private? realm of liberty, is therefore not really neutral but is instead a stance that simply pays deference to the status quo power structure of gender and sexuality. The liberal ideology fails to recognize that politics is at stake not simply in who will be elected or how state power will be exercised, but more fundamentally in how our everyday social roles are constructed and repro- duced. Both sides of the liberal dualisms?that every- thing can be understood fundamentally as public or private, subjective or objective, individual or social?- exclude the possibility that social relations are never either ?chosen? or neutral, but rather are socially con- structed and thus bear the marks of a history of struggle and the contingencies of a future that could be different. Liberalism began as a critique of power, but in both its intellectual and everyday ideology its vision of where power is exercised has been limited to the formalized state. But power is at stake across existential space: in sexuality, in workplaces, in schools, in hallways and on street corners, and in the myriad social hierarchies within which we ?nd ourselves. Instead of responding to the widespread and unfulfilled need people have to feel a part of their social lives, contemporary liberal discourse understands reform only in the sense of remedying the exceptional discrimination, and therefore it fails to con- nect the domination of the victims of ?discrimination? to the widespread powerlessness people feel that their social lives are beyond their control or influence. A new, transformative politics must recognize this broader agenda and thereby connect .the widely experienced pain and estrangement of masses of Americans to the particular struggles on behalf of the poor, minorities, and women. To some, crossing the borders of liberal ideology means ?collective tyranny,? where the state will regulate every aspect of our private and public lives according to the whim of the majority. Tikkun politics thus seems to threaten whatever freedom our liberal culture has achieved. But we recognize that the liberal tradition has helped institutionalize important freedoms. We don?t think that people should be thrown in jail for expressing their views or that kids in school should be forced to pray to others? deities. But we also don?t think that it is desirable to render public schools, and the public world generally, antiseptic, impersonal, and alienating to who we are and where we come from. Each attempt to achieve a neutral public life has actually produced new castes separating the secular, the reasonable, the cos- mopolitan, and the enlightened from the religious, the redneck, the uneducated, and the parochial. In short, the fear of ?collective tyranny? ignores the ways that our social relations are already collectivized according to the liberal discourse of power that poses as objectivity itself. Our freedom cannot depend on enforcing borders between the public and the private, because drawing the borders is itself a political decision to regulate with one form of social power rather than another. Protecting ?private? economic rights in tradi- tional liberalism meant exposing ordinary working people to the ?collective tyranny? of the economically powerful; protecting the privacy of family relations means exposing women to the tyranny of patriarchal power. Moreover, seeing ?collective tyranny? in attempts to uncover the suppressed politics of everyday life betrays a narrow attitude toward politics?a vision of politics in which the only means of exercising social choice is TIKKUN AND PROGRESSIVE LIBERALISM 81 by voting for one candidate or another. But politics could mean more than voters choosing a central govern- ment out there. It could mean being engaged, all of us, together, in the construction of our social roles as we live them day to day in the institutions in which we ?nd ourselves. We want to help articulate a politics that responds to the powerlessness that people feel in their everyday lives, that comprehends all the places where power is at stake, and that reinspires us to believe that we can remake the world. We want to resist the liberal border patrol that tells us that our subjective and particular values are inappropriate for public discourse and that our personal lives are simply the result of autonomous choice. Part of this project means articulating progressive PAPER: RELIGIOUS FUNDAMENTALISM legislative proposals and engaging in electoral campaigns. But such activities can also con?rm the alienating sense people have of the world?s being ruled by alien forces unless these activities are connected with a transforma- tive vision of a shared social struggle to recover power and meaning in everyday life. We want to overcome the sense that the public world of politics stands outside ourselves as some abstract and distant community. Thus we reject the arti?cial association of the spiritual and the moral with the private sphere. We want to spiritualize the political world and politicize the private one. It is time to recognize that the liberal borders themselves enforce a colonization of everyday life. An earlier version of this paper was given at the Tikhun conference. The Real Issue Behind Who-Is-a-Jew David Biale ith the formation of a new national unity coalition between Likud and Labor, the Who-Is-a-Jew issue has once again been relegated to the political back burner, a development that American Jewish organizations will no doubt regard as a great victory. But this immediate achieve- ment should not obscure the fact that more profound underlying issues remain unsolved and that what appears on the surface to be a victory may conceal cancerous self-delusion. There was a striking irony in the rush of American Jewish leaders to criticize Israel publicly and even to mobilize non-Jewish members of Congress to pressure Israeli leaders over the issue of Who-Is-a-Jew. In many cases, the very same leaders who viciously condemned those who had raised questions about the occupation of the territories and the handling of the Palestinian uprising were among the most vocal about Who-Isa- Jew. When a symbol of their ostensible self-interest was at stake, they had no compunction about ?Israel-bashing? (to use their favorite pejorative), but when it is Palestinian children who are being beaten, beatings that can scarcely David Biale is director of the Center for Jewish Studies and a professor of Jewish history at the Graduate Theological Union in Berkeley, California. His latest hook is Power and Power- lessness in Jewish History (Schoeken, 1986). A Hebrew version of this article appeared in the Israeli journal Politika. 82 TIKKUN VOL. 4, N0. 4 be called symbolic, their moral sensibility fails them. Who-Is-a-Jew was much more important to them than the real question: What is a Jewish state? But moral issues aside, American Jewish leaders got it wrong, even from the point of View of pure self-interest. Judging from the concern that these leaders evince over Reform and Conservative conversions, one would think that tens of thousands of American Jews were immi- grating to Israel every year. In truth, no more than a handful of converts would be affected by a change in the Law of Return. Of course, it could be argued that a change in the law might affect Diaspora Jews in the event that anti-Semitism were to create the need for a mass exodus to Israel. But such a claim is the last thing that American Jews wish to advance in public, nor is it, in any case, likely. The intifada, on the other hand, has the potential to affect quite vitally the self-interest of American Jews. One might imagine a scenario in which Israel adopts more and more extreme policies to suppress the Pales- tinians, including mass expulsions. At the same time, the PLO continues to develop its political initiative, calling for a two?state solution. The United States, which has now ?nally begun contacts with the PLO, becomes thoroughly fed up with Israeli intransigence and begins to apply serious pressure. American Jews, in such an event, w0uld ?nd themselves politically isolated and